Results for 'A. David Hitchcock'

1000+ found
Order:
  1. Arguing as Trying to Show That a Target-claim is Correct.A. David Hitchcock - 2011 - Theoria: Revista de Teoría, Historia y Fundamentos de la Ciencia 26 (3):301-310.
    En Giving Reasons, Bermejo-Luque sostiene correctamente que un modelo normativo del acto de habla de la argumentación es más defendible si se basa en un objetivo interno constitutivo del acto de argumentar, que si se apoya en objetivos que que uno no necesita perseguir cuando argumenta, tal como, en su opinión, sucede con otros modelos normativos. Ella identifica correctamente argumentar con intentar justificar. Pero no está claro que haya acertado al identificar como objetivo interno de la argumentación el mostrar que (...)
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  2.  32
    On Reasoning and Argument: Essays in Informal Logic and on Critical Thinking.David Hitchcock - 2017 - Cham, Switzerland: Springer Verlag.
    This book brings together in one place David Hitchcock’s most significant published articles on reasoning and argument. In seven new chapters he updates his thinking in the light of subsequent scholarship. Collectively, the papers articulate a distinctive position in the philosophy of argumentation. Among other things, the author:• develops an account of “material consequence” that permits evaluation of inferences without problematic postulation of unstated premises.• updates his recursive definition of argument that accommodates chaining and embedding of arguments and (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   31 citations  
  3.  8
    Critical Thinking: A Guide to Evaluating Information.David Hitchcock - 1983 - Taylor & Francis.
  4.  79
    Fallacies and formal logic in Aristotle.David Hitchcock - 2000 - History and Philosophy of Logic 21 (3):207-221.
    The taxonomy and analysis of fallacies in Aristotle's Sophistical Refutations pre-date the formal logic of his Prior Analytics A4-6. Of the 64 fully described examples of ?sophistical refutations? which are fallacious because they are only apparently valid, 49 have the wrong number of premisses or the wrong form of premiss or conclusion for analysis by the Prior Analytics theory of the categorical syllogism. The rest Aristotle either frames so that they do not look like categorical syllogisms or analyses in a (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  5.  16
    Arguing on the Toulmin Model: New Essays in Argument Analysis and Evaluation.David Hitchcock & Bart Verheij (eds.) - 2006 - Dordrecht, Netherland: Springer.
    In The Uses of Argument, Stephen Toulmin proposed a model for the layout of arguments: claim, data, warrant, qualifier, rebuttal, backing. Since then, Toulmin’s model has been appropriated, adapted and extended by researchers in speech communications, philosophy and artificial intelligence. This book assembles the best contemporary reflection in these fields, extending or challenging Toulmin’s ideas in ways that make fresh contributions to the theory of analysing and evaluating arguments.
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  6.  42
    Does the Traditional Treatment of Enthymemes Rest on a Mistake?David Hitchcock - 1998 - Argumentation 12 (1):15-37.
    In many actual arguments, the conclusion seems intuitively to follow from the premisses, even though we cannot show that it follows logically. The traditional approach to evaluating such arguments is to suppose that they have an unstated premiss whose explicit addition will produce an argument where the conclusion does follow logically. But there are good reasons for doubting that people so frequently leave the premisses of their arguments unstated. The inclination to suppose that they do stems from the belief that (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   56 citations  
  7.  24
    A Framework for Deliberation Dialogues.David Hitchcock, Peter Mcburney & Simon Parsons - unknown
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  8.  49
    Definition: A practical guide to constructing and evaluating definitions of terms.David Hitchcock - 2021 - Windsor, ON: Windsor Studies in Argumentation.
    This book proposes guidelines for constructing and evaluating definitions of terms, i.e. words or phrases of general application. The guidelines extend to adoption of nomenclature. The book is meant to be a practical guide for people who find themselves in their daily lives or their employment producing or evaluating definitions of terms. It can be consulted rather than being read through. The book’s theoretical framework is a distinction, due to Robert H. Ennis, of three dimensions of definitions: the act of (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  9.  15
    Sampling scholarly arguments: a test of a theory of good inference.David Hitchcock - unknown
  10.  12
    So.David Hitchcock - unknown
    I argue, contrary to a recent assertion by Lilian Bermejo-Luque, that the inference-claim in an argument of the form ‘p, so q’ is not its associated material conditional ‘if p then q’. Rather, it is the claim that the argument has a covering generalization that is non-trivially true. I defend this interpretation against three objections by Bermejo-Luque.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  11.  64
    Inference Claims.David Hitchcock - 2011 - Informal Logic 31 (3):191-229.
    A conclusion follows from given premisses if and only if an acceptable counterfactual-supporting covering generalization of the argument rules out, either definitively or with some modal qualification, simultaneous acceptability of the premisses and non-accepta-bility of the conclusion, even though it does not rule out acceptability of the premisses and does not require acceptability of the conclusion independently of the premisses. Hence the reiterative associated conditional of an argument is true if and only it has such a covering generalization, and a (...)
    Direct download (16 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   16 citations  
  12.  75
    The Practice of Argumentative Discussion.David Hitchcock - 2002 - Argumentation 16 (3):287-298.
    I propose some changes to the conceptions of argument and of argumentative discussion in Ralph Johnson's Manifest Rationality (2000). An argument is a discourse whose author seeks to persuade an audience to accept a thesis by producing reasons in support of it and discharging his dialectical obligations. An argumentative discussion (what Johnson calls ‘argumentation’) is a sociocultural activity of constructing, presenting, interpreting, criticizing, and revising arguments for the purpose of reaching a shared rationally supported position on some issue. Johnson's theory (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   23 citations  
  13.  9
    The Culture of Spoken Arguments.David Hitchcock - unknown
    37 arguments were selected by random sampling methods from calls to radio and television phone-in programs. I discuss whether my general theory of inference evaluation applies to them and how frequently they exemplify a recognized argument scheme. I also compare their dependence on context, their complexity and their quality to those features of a previously studied sample of 50 scholarly arguments.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   6 citations  
  14.  28
    A note on implicit premisses.David Hitchcock - 2002 - Informal Logic 22 (2).
  15.  39
    Relevance.David Hitchcock - 1992 - Argumentation 6 (2):251-270.
    Relevance is a triadic relation between an item, an outcome or goal, and a situation. Causal relevance consists in an item's ability to help produce an outcome in a situation. Epistemic relevance, a distinct concept, consists in the ability of a piece of information (or a speech act communicating or requesting a piece of information) to help achieve an epistemic goal in a situation. It has this ability when it can be ineliminably combined with other at least potentially accurate information (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   20 citations  
  16.  10
    Material consequences and counter-factuals.David Hitchcock - unknown
    A conclusion is a “material consequence” of reasons if it follows necessarily from them in accordance with a valid form of argument with content. The corresponding universal generalization of the argument’s associated conditional must be true, must be a covering generalization, and must be true of counter-factual instances. But it need not be law-like. Pearl’s structural model semantics is easier to apply to such counter-factual instances than Lewis’s closest-worlds semantics, and gives intuitively correct results.
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  17.  80
    Good Reasoning on the Toulmin Model.David Hitchcock - 2005 - Argumentation 19 (3):373-391.
    Some solo verbal reasoning serves the function of arriving at a correct answer to a question from information at the reasoner’s disposal. Such reasoning is good if and only if its grounds are justified and adequate, its warrant is justified, and the reasoner is justified in assuming that no defeaters apply. I distinguish seven sources of justified grounds and state the conditions under which each source is trustworthy. Adequate grounds include all good relevant information practically obtainable by the reasoner. The (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   17 citations  
  18.  8
    Did Jesus Commit a Fallacy?David Hitchcock - unknown
    No categories
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  19.  80
    Appeals to Considerations.David Hitchcock - 2013 - Informal Logic 33 (2):195-237.
    Wellman’s “conduction” and Govier’s “conductive arguments” are best described as appeals to considerations. The considerations cited are features of a subject of interest, and the conclusion is the attribution to it of a supervenient status like a classification, an evaluation, a prescription or an interpretation. The conclusion may follow either conclusively or non-conclusively or not at all. Weighing the pros and cons is only one way of judging whether the conclusion follows. Further, the move from in-formation about the subject’s cited (...)
    Direct download (15 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   9 citations  
  20.  45
    The Significance of Informal Logic for Philosophy.David Hitchcock - 2000 - Informal Logic 20 (2).
    Informal logic is a new sub-discipline of philosophy, roughly definable as the philosophy of argument. Contributors have challenged the traditional concept of an argument as a premiss-conclusion complex, in favour of speech-act, functional and dialogical conceptions; they have identified as additional components warrants, modal qualifiers, rebuttals, and a dialectical tier. They have objected that "soundness" is neither necessary nor sufficient for a good argument. Alternative proposals include acceptability, relevance and sufficiency of the premisses; conformity to a valid argument schema; conformity (...)
    Direct download (12 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
  21.  29
    The pragma-dialectical analysis of the ad hominem fallacy.David Hitchcock - 2006 - In F. H. van Eemeren, Peter Houtlosser, Haft-van Rees & A. M. (eds.), Considering pragma-dialectics: a festschrift for Frans H. van Eemeren on the occasion of his 60th birthday. Mahwah, N.J.: L. Erlbaum Associates. pp. 103.
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   5 citations  
  22.  40
    Pollock on Practical Reasoning.David Hitchcock - 2002 - Informal Logic 22 (3).
    The epistemologist John Pollock has implemented computationally an architecture for a rational agent which he calls OSCAR. OSCAR models both practical and theoretical (or epistemic) reasoning. I argue that Pollock's model of practical reasoning, which has seven components, is superior not only to the two-component belief-desire model stemming from Aristotle, but also to the three-component belief-desire-intention model developed especially by Michael Bratman. Despite its advantages, Pollock's model of practical reasoning is incomplete in at least three respects: it is solipsistic, it (...)
    Direct download (13 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   12 citations  
  23.  19
    Transsubjectivity.David Hitchcock - 2017 - Informal Logic 37 (3):230-239.
    I describe and evaluate Harald Wohlrapp’s proposal in The Concept of Argument that we should see reasonable argumentation as guided by the “principle of transsubjectivity... that, beginning with my subjectivity, I put my actual ego up for consideration as well as heighten and transcend it by seeking to participate in a general human potential, which is only attainable by recognizing the subjectivity of the Other”, and thus as having a quasi-religious meaning.
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   4 citations  
  24.  50
    The Effectiveness of Computer Assisted Instruction in Critical Thinking.David Hitchcock - 2004 - Informal Logic 24 (3):183-217.
    278 non-freshman university students taking a l2-week critical thinking course in a large single-section class, with computer-assisted guided practice as a replacement for small-group discussion, and all testing in machine-scored multiple-choice format, improved their critical thinking skills, as measured by the California Critical Thinking Skills Test, by half a standard deviation, a moderate improvement. The improvement was more than that reported with a traditional format without computer-assisted instruction, but less than that reported with a format using both computer-assisted instruction and (...)
    Direct download (15 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   10 citations  
  25.  7
    A Theory of Argument Appraisal.David Hitchcock - 1988 - Philosophie Et Culture: Actes du XVIIe Congrès Mondial de Philosophie 2:821-827.
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  26.  29
    Freeman's Syntactic Criterion for Linkage.David Hitchcock - 2015 - Informal Logic 35 (4):1-31.
    Freeman’s syntactic criterion for linked argument structure is often readily applicable, captures intuitively linked structures, and implies that refuting a single premiss of a linked argument suffices to refute the argument. But one cannot sharply separate analysis from inference evaluation in applying it, whether an argument satisfies it can be uncertain, it under-generates cases where refuting one premiss suffices to refute an argument, some arguments satisfying it can be easily rescued if a single premiss is refuted, and Freeman’s underlying account (...)
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  27.  22
    Tarski’s Theory of the Formal Correctness of Definitions.David Hitchcock - 2024 - Journal of Philosophical Logic 53 (1):181-221.
    In his 1933 monograph on the concept of truth, Alfred Tarski claimed that his definition of truth satisfied “the usual conditions of methodological correctness”, which in a 1935 article he identified as consistency and back-translatability. Following the rules of defining for an axiomatized theory was supposed to ensure satisfaction of the two conditions. But Tarski neither explained the two conditions nor supplied rules of defining for any axiomatized theory. We can make explicit what Tarski understood by consistency and back-translatability, with (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  28.  75
    Arguing as Trying to Show That a Target-claim is Correct.David Hitchcock - 2011 - Theoria 26 (3):301-309.
    In Giving Reasons, Bermejo-Luque rightly claims that a normative model of the speech act of argumentation is more defensible if it rests on an internal aim that is constitutive of the act of arguing than if it rests, as she claims existing normative models do, on an aim that one need not pursue when one argues. She rightly identifies arguing with trying to justify something. But it is not so clear that she has correctly identified the internal aim of arguing (...)
    Direct download (7 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  29.  29
    The origin of the technical use of "sound argument": a postscript.David Hitchcock - 1999 - Informal Logic 19 (2).
  30.  4
    Commentary on: James B. Freeman's "What types of arguments are there?".David Hitchcock - unknown
  31.  20
    Response to my commentator.David Hitchcock - unknown
  32.  18
    Enumerative Induction.David Hitchcock - unknown
    In an enumerative induction we project a property found in all the examined members of a class to a hitherto unexamined member of that class. I consider an unresolved disagreement between Stephen Thomas and John Nolt about how likely the conclusion of one example of such reasoning is, given the premisses. Reflection on their controversy, and on the example, indicates that many textbook commonplaces about enumerative inductions are false. In particular, uniformity of the examined members of a class does not (...)
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  33.  9
    John L. Pollock's theory of rationality.David Hitchcock - unknown
    Pollock is developing, and testing computationally a theory of rationality. I endorse his claim that the structure of argument is not always linear, his replacement of the deductive-inductive distinction with a deductive-defeasible distinction, and hi s distinction between rebutting defeaters, and undercutting defeaters. I question the absence of pragmatic constraints in his acceptance rule, an absence which fits ill with his criterion of interruptibility, that it is reasonable to act on the conclusions drawn at any point. I also wonder about (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  34.  25
    Justifying Questions: What Kinds, How, and Why.David Hitchcock - 2021 - In Moritz Cordes (ed.), Asking and Answering: Rivalling Approaches to Interrogative Methods. Tübingen: Narr Francke Attempto. pp. 139–155.
    The authors of 200 arguments for questions posed 19 types of questions, justified them in 62 different ways, offered a justification of the question for 50 different types of purposes, and posed the question for 49 different types of purposes. Further consolidation of the categories used in the analysis is desirable and possible. Of the six most commonly posed types of questions, only three (yes-no questions, select questions, and either-or questions) are at first glance capable of formal representation in an (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  35.  64
    The Thomas-Nolt Dispute: Some Lessons about Induction.David Hitchcock - 1999 - Informal Logic 19 (2).
    I resolve an apparently unresolved dispute about how probable uniform experience makes an extrapolation from it, and draw some general lessons about such enumerative induction. Uniform experience does not necessarily confer a high probability on an extrapolation of or generalization from that experience. Rational extrapolation or generalization typically involves a lot of specific background information, though not necessarily a general assumption that nature is uniform or that the future will resemble the past. And new evidence which is highly likely on (...)
    Direct download (13 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  36.  44
    Harald R. Wohlrapp: The Concept of Argument: A Philosophical Foundation. Logic, Argumentation and Reasoning 4.David Hitchcock - 2016 - Argumentation 30 (3):353-363.
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  37.  22
    Textbook Treatments of Fallacies.David Hitchcock - 2023 - Argumentation 37 (2):233-245.
    In his Fallacies, Hamblin (1970) castigated what he called the “standard treatment” of fallacies in introductory textbooks of his day as debased, worn-out, dogmatic, and unconnected to anything else in modern logic. A bit more than 50 years later, I investigate the treatment of fallacies in six English-language introductory textbooks with a section on fallacies that have gone into 10 or more editions, to see whether their treatment of fallacies has taken account of the scholarship on fallacies that Hamblin’s book (...)
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  38. The good in Plato's "republic".David Hitchcock - 1985 - Apeiron 19 (2):65 - 92.
    After clarifying what plato means by "the good," noting accounts of the good which he explicitly rejects in the "republic", and carefully interpreting the comparison of the good with the sun at "republic" 508-509, this paper infers from the comparison that the good is unity. It then examines the coherence of this account with what the "republic" says about the foundations of mathematics and about the good of individuals and of cities, and offers a preliminary appraisal.
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   1 citation  
  39.  16
    Arguing for Questions.David Hitchcock - 2019 - In Bart Garssen & Frans van Eemeren (eds.), From Argument Schemes to Argumentative Relations in the Wild: A Variety of Contributions to Argumentation Theory. Cham, Switzerland: Springer Verlag. pp. 167-184.
    People sometimes argue for questions, as can be verified by a Web search using as search terms phrases consisting of a conclusion indicator and an interrogative particle. These arguments provide a reason for asking the question and thus try to establish that it needs to be answered. Typically, they do so either in order to motivate interest in discovering the answer or in order to challenge addressees or a third party to explain their behaviour. The “inferential erotetic logic” of the (...)
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  40.  57
    The Structure of Being in Aristotle’s Metaphysics. [REVIEW]David Hitchcock - 2005 - Review of Metaphysics 58 (4):924-925.
    The per se beings are those signified by the ultimate predicates in species–genus hierarchies: what a thing is, quality, quantity, relation, and so forth. Understanding change requires the investigation of the potential versus actual existence of any such per se being. Yu argues that Aristotle’s references in his central text on the focal structure of being to process, generation, and destruction imply that substance is the focus not only of the other per se beings but also of potential versus actual (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  41.  11
    Book Review of Is that a Fact? [REVIEW]David Hitchcock - 2011 - Informal Logic 31 (1):66-68.
  42.  32
    Andrew Aberdein and Ian J. Dove (eds): The Argument of Mathematics (Logic, Epistemology and the Unity of Science, Vol. 30): Springer, Dordrecht, The Netherlands, 2013, x + 393 pp. [REVIEW]David Hitchcock - 2014 - Argumentation 28 (2):245-258.
    Post-war argumentation theorists have tended to regard argumentation as one thing and mathematical proof as another. Perelman (1958, 1969), for example, defined the word ‘argumentation’ stipulatively as a contrast term to ‘demonstration’: whereas mathematical reasoning as theorized by modern formal logic, he writes, is a matter of deducing theorems from axioms in accordance with stipulated rules of transformation, argumentation aims at gaining the adherence of minds (Perelman 1969, pp. 1–2). Toulmin (1958) contrasted his “jurisprudential model” of argument, according to which (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  43.  3
    Lewis on Causation.Christopher Hitchcock - 2015 - In Barry Loewer & Jonathan Schaffer (eds.), A Companion to David Lewis. Oxford, UK: Wiley. pp. 295–311.
    This chapter focuses on the connection between counterfactuals and causation, and on the use of causation in the analyses of other concepts, especially decision and dispositions. It briefly reviews two preliminary pieces of conceptual apparatus. The chapter divides Lewis's treatment of causation into three stages: The first is the theory presented in the 1973 paper "Causation.” The second includes the amendments included in postscripts to “Causation” in Philosophical Papers, Volume II, in 1986.The final stage is the theory from "Causation as (...)
    No categories
    Direct download  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   2 citations  
  44.  28
    Making a Difference: Essays on the Philosophy of Causation Edited by Helen Beebee, Christopher Hitchcock and Huw Price.David Westland - 2019 - Analysis 79 (3):578-581.
    Making a Difference: Essays on the Philosophy of Causation Edited by BeebeeHelen, HitchcockChristopher and PriceHuwOxford University Press, 2017. xii + 336 pp.
    No categories
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  45. Re-Visiting the Double: A Girardian Reading of Alfred Hitchcock’s Rope and Strangers on a Train.David Humbert - 2013 - Contagion: Journal of Violence, Mimesis, and Culture 20:253-261.
    No categories
    Direct download (3 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  46.  39
    Desire and Monstrosity in the Disaster Film: Alfred Hitchcock's The Birds.David Humbert - 2010 - Contagion: Journal of Violence, Mimesis, and Culture 17:87-103.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Desire and Monstrosity in the Disaster Film:Alfred Hitchcock's The BirdsDavid Humbert (bio)The theme of the relationship between desire and violence appears regularly in modern film criticism, and studies of this issue range in theoretical orientation from the Lacanian to the feminist.1 Though René Girard's view of this relationship is also regularly mentioned in studies of film violence, it is often with less than full appreciation of the way (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark  
  47.  66
    Edward Hitchcock’s Pre-Darwinian “Tree of Life”.J. David Archibald - 2009 - Journal of the History of Biology 42 (3):561 - 592.
    The "tree of life" iconography, representing the history of life, dates from at least the latter half of the 18th century, but evolution as the mechanism providing this bifurcating history of life did not appear until the early 19th century. There was also a shift from the straight line, scala naturae view of change in nature to a more bifurcating or tree-like view. Throughout the 19th century authors presented tree-like diagrams, some regarding the Deity as the mechanism of change while (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  48.  21
    Edward Hitchcock’s Pre-Darwinian “Tree of Life”.J. David Archibald - 2009 - Journal of the History of Biology 42 (3):561-592.
    The "tree of life" iconography, representing the history of life, dates from at least the latter half of the 18th century, but evolution as the mechanism providing this bifurcating history of life did not appear until the early 19th century. There was also a shift from the straight line, scala naturae view of change in nature to a more bifurcating or tree-like view. Throughout the 19th century authors presented tree-like diagrams, some regarding the Deity as the mechanism of change while (...)
    Direct download (2 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   3 citations  
  49. Causation, Norm violation, and culpable control.Mark D. Alicke, David Rose & Dori Bloom - 2011 - Journal of Philosophy 108 (12):670-696.
    Causation is one of philosophy's most venerable and thoroughly-analyzed concepts. However, the study of how ordinary people make causal judgments is a much more recent addition to the philosophical arsenal. One of the most prominent views of causal explanation, especially in the realm of harmful or potentially harmful behavior, is that unusual or counternormative events are accorded privileged status in ordinary causal explanations. This is a fundamental assumption in psychological theories of counterfactual reasoning, and has been transported to philosophy by (...)
    Direct download (4 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   76 citations  
  50.  67
    The Logical Impossibility of Collision.A. David Kline & Carl A. Matheson - 1987 - Philosophy 62 (242):509 - 515.
    Absolutely no one still believes that every physical interactionconsists of material bodies bumping into each other. Those who have tried to work out a completely mechanistic physics have been unable to explain common phenomena like liquidity, gravitation and magnetism. In fact, there is great reason to doubt that such a physics could ever account for attractive forces in general.
    No categories
    Direct download (5 more)  
     
    Export citation  
     
    Bookmark   14 citations  
1 — 50 / 1000